We may agree on what something is, even if we disagree
on how it should be described. We may both be looking at a circle; you may
describe it as having a circumference of a particular length, while I may
describe it as having a radius of a particular length.
Do we have to agree on how to describe what “reasonable
doubt” means? Does it have a utilitarian or a pragmatic function; is it a
quality like “good” (remembering GE Moore’s difficulty in defining “good”). Does
it have a function at all, or is it just a feeling?
Is it describable in terms of knowledge? To ask “what
do I know” is to summon the ideas of knowledge and belief. What are the
conditions that I require to be satisfied before I am prepared to say I believe
something? Do I rely on experience, feeling, logic, or persuasive rhetoric? Do
I have to use the same criteria for belief as you use?
Often juries will ask judges for a definition of “beyond
reasonable doubt”. While courts may differ in their responses, do their
differences conceal an agreement?
I have previously discussed the leading New Zealand case on this: R v Wanhalla [2006]
NZCA 229; [2007] 2 NZLR 573. Now the High Court of Australia has
considered the same issue: The Queen v
Dookheea [2017]
HCA 36 (13 September 2017).
The HCA
prefers that explanations of what proof beyond reasonable doubt means should
not be attempted, and in particular a contrast with proof beyond any doubt
should be avoided. It is, however, acceptable and even useful to contrast the
high criminal standard of proof beyond reasonable doubt with the lower civil
standard of proof on the balance of probabilities. “[A] reasonable doubt is a
doubt which the jury as a reasonable jury considers to be reasonable (albeit,
of course, that different jurors might have different reasons for their own
reasonable doubt)” (at [34]), and ([35]):
“... it is the votes of each of the individual
members of the jury that are determinative of the verdict of the jury as a
whole. Each juror is appointed to consider the evidence and to decide whether
it satisfies him or her of guilt beyond reasonable doubt; and, in order to
discharge that function, each individual member of the jury must in effect
enquire of himself or herself whether he or she entertains a reasonable doubt.
In practical reality, each individual juror may at some point in the course of
the juror's consideration of an issue have a doubt which, upon reflection and
evaluation, he or she is disposed to discard as an unreasonable doubt.”
Clumsily
put, if one objects
to unnecessary gender pronouns, but there you are.
In New
Zealand, explanations of beyond reasonable doubt may be attempted: acceptable
is, “an honest and reasonable uncertainty left in your mind about the guilt of
the accused after you have given careful and impartial consideration to all of
the evidence.” But this is not mandatory, and it “is sufficient to make it
clear that the concept [of proof beyond reasonable doubt] involves a high
standard of proof which is discharged only if the jury is sure or feels sure of
guilt.” Focusing on doubt may be misleading, because a doubt need not be
articulable and what is required is proof to the required standard. It is
acceptable to tell a jury that proof to a certainty is not required. But it is
wrong to tell a jury that they need to be as sure of guilt as they would be
about an important decision in their own lives.
Utilitarianism asks, what is in the best interests of
society? Individual interests are subordinate to society’s interests,
individual rights are minimised, and as far as crime is concerned, a deterrent
policy is pursued to protect the peace of the community. On the topic of the
criminal standard of proof, a utilitarian would acknowledge that it must be
higher than the civil standard, but not all that much higher.
A pragmatist would ask, what works? The ends justify
the means. Pragmatism may strive for a workable balance between utilitarianism
and morality. While absolute proof of a criminal charge is not required, pragmatism
justifies a high, but not too high, standard of proof.
A moral view (and here I acknowledge that these are all moral theories, but I just say "moral" here to avoid having to say deontological) is that it is better to let (insert your
preferred number) guilty people go free than to convict one innocent person. It
reflects a judgement about what is right or good in the context of a criminal
trial, and it favours a very high standard of proof.
These themes are found in the various approaches to
instructions on the standard of proof. To say that the standard is higher than
the civil standard is to make a utilitarian point. It doesn’t get very far by
way of explanation, but it is a start. To add that the fact-finder must “be
sure” on a “reasonable” assessment of the evidence, is a pragmatic theme,
taking the explanation beyond the utilitarian but not pushing it as far as
morality would claim it should be taken. Also pragmatic is the illustration of
taking the care one would take over an important decision in one’s own life. To
say that proof to a mathematical certainty is not required but the standard is
nevertheless very high, is to emphasise the moral theme.
You can't really be surprised when a jury wants assistance with the concept of proof beyond reasonable doubt. Nor at the reluctance of judges to get into the extent to which deontological ethics may be modified by pragmatism. It should be reassuring, however, to remember that philosophy is just simple ideas dressed up in hard words, in contrast to law which is hard ideas dressed up in simple words.